There are few doctrines more maligned or misunderstood than that of the impassibility of God—the idea that God cannot be made to suffer change from without or be overcome with passions.
Since the early Fathers this has been the standard teaching of the Church: God is not subject to passions. I first found out about this idea in college when reading Jurgen Moltmann’s classic, The Crucified God in which he argues that for God to be impassible in light of the world’s suffering and evil would make God wicked. In fact, in light of the cross of Christ where the Godman suffers death and alienation, impassibility is absolutely blasphemous. Instead, the Bible presents us with a passionate God who suffers alongside of us, who bleeds, who dies, and who understands our pains—because isn’t that what love does? In this account, impassibility is a hold-over from Greek philosophy, which crept in and corrupted the pure, Hebrew view of the dynamic, living God of Scripture and turned it into the conceptual idol of the frozen absolute valued by Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics.
This view, that of the passible God, has become the “New Orthodoxy” that has been growing apace in academic and popular theology since the earliest part of the twentieth century, especially with the rise of process theism, open theism, and panentheism. Impassibility has also been rejected in various quarters of evangelical theology that cling to otherwise traditional doctrines of God, with John Stott citing Moltmann on this point with approval in his great work, The Cross of Christ. Given that many first encounter the doctrine of impassibility without any real knowledge of historical theology, or of the Fathers’s reasoning for articulating this doctrine, it is easy to see why it has been commonly rejected as the silly invention of “Greek” theologians and their systematizing ways.
Yet there have also been significant criticisms of passibilist logic from biblical, theological, philosophical, and historical-theological angles, like those by Thomas Weinandy, Kevin Vanhoozer, David Bentley Hart, and Paul Gavrilyuk.
While I won’t attempt to cover all the relevant points I want to offer up a few key correctives of popular perceptions of the doctrine, as well as offer some reasons to find this doctrine beautiful along the way.
Clarifying Thoughts on Impassibility
Not a Rock
Critics often contend that the doctrine of impassibility depicts God as an emotionless rock. But to teach that God is impassible is not to deny that God has an emotional life with cares, joys, loves, and so forth. Impassibility does not mean impassivity any more than immutability means immobility. Both are caricatures and misunderstandings of the classical doctrine. Just as the doctrine of God’s immutability or changelessness is not a teaching about a static, stone God, but a God so perfectly overflowing with life that any “change” could only tend towards a lesser state, so the doctrine of impassibility is statement about the perfection of God’s emotional life, his sovereignty over it, rather than its absence. In the early Fathers, to teach that God was impassible was to teach that God did not have “passions”, or unrestrained feelings ungoverned by reason or will that could simply sweep over him. A passion was thought of as a sort of violent, semi-physical force that could move a person without the consent of their reason or will. To deny that this can happen is to say that God’s emotional life is under his own control and will not erupt violently in irrational or sinful ways. In other words, God is not an emotional teenager.
The Bible?
What about those passages in the Bible that talk about God’s very strong feelings about things? What do they point to if God is not a passionate God? Are they “merely” anthropomorphisms that don’t “really” mean what they say? The Fathers and the medieval tradition made a distinction between ‘passions’ and ‘affections.’ An affection is a sort of controlled emotion that is subject to the will and mind of the one having it. It is a rational emotion that does not overcome the person, but is in line with the will. God has affections such as kindness, anger, etc. which he can display. The passages in the Bible talking about God’s anger, kindness, grief, and so forth are pointing to something real in God—his affections, the emotional life of the God of Israel. They are not “mere” anthropomorphisms, even though they are anthropomorphic. They are real descriptions, though not to be taken in a literalistic fashion, of God’s emotional life.
What’s An Emotion Anyway?
One point that clouds this discussion and makes it hard to conceive of God having emotions that are not passions, is that we often don’t have a clear understanding of what an emotion is. Kevin Vanhoozer draws attention to the fact that there are various theories on offer as to what an emotion is, but that there are two basic ways of construing them: non-cognitivist and cognitivist understandings. Non-cognitivist theories of emotion stress the sub-rational nature of an emotion, like the physical rush associated with fear or anger, which we then attach to cognitive content. Vanhoozer points out a few problems with that. First, God is spiritual, not physical. He cannot have an adrenaline rush with a flush of the face, a flaring of the nostrils, or moistening of the tear-ducts. For us to ascribe emotions to him on this view is to ascribe a body. The second problem with this is that with fear or anger, I feel the rush precisely because of what I believe about a certain situation or action. Third, a lot of emotions “feel” the same physically, like anger and fear, but the only thing distinguishing them is the cognitive content. Fourth, it’s hard to ascribe praise or blame to the way people feel if it’s just a physical reaction. But we seem to think that some feelings are praiseworthy and others are blameworthy (cf. racial anger, schadenfreude, or jealousy at the good fortune of others). For these reasons, (and a few others), its best to opt for a cognitivist understanding of emotion.
On a cognitivist view, an emotion is a judgment or an attitude that one takes about something. It is a concern-based, value-laden judgment about a state of affairs. My fear and happiness are flavored understandings about situations or persons that I am concerned with. Given my humanity, my loves, jealousy, or fear can be both passions that I suffer as well as affections. We are both patients and agents with respect to them. God has perfect emotions, affections not passions, because his value-laden judgments are true and accurate ones. God’s love, jealousy, wrath, compassion, and kindness are involved judgments, ways of “seeing” with the heart that inclines him towards action of some sort but do not overwhelm him. They do not incline him towards evil and they cannot sweep over him because they are fully-consonant with his perfect knowledge and will.
For many, these highly cognitive emotions will likely seem too distant from our everyday human experience. In response, Vanhoozer would remind us that “the similarities between God’s emotional life and ours exist in the midst of an even greater dissimilarity, one that marks the infinite qualitative distinction between Creator and creation, Author and hero.” God is God. We might be made in his image, but God’s reality is a whole ontological step up from ours. We should expect things to be different up there. Just as God’s sense of personhood will be different than yours given that he exists as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, while you exist as you, it’s unsurprising that his emotional life is a little beyond us.
Sovereign Relationality
A further consideration connected to impassibility is that there is nothing outside of God that is beyond his control. Those agents or situations about which he feels things are not outside of his will or agency. Given_creatio ex nihilo, _even with a strong view of libertarian human agency, God is not subject to his human creations. His feelings in relation to them are not things that he must passively suffer but ones which he actively chooses to endure. They are not imposed on him from without, but sovereignly accepted. Passibilists might point to passages like Hosea 11:8, where God speaks to Israel, saying that he cannot bear to be parted from him, that his heart recoils within him at the thought of extinguishing him in judgment. The thought is that here human subjects exert a force and cause a change, or suffering in the emotional life of God from without. But these statements are uttered within the context of a covenant relationship which God freely and sovereignly entered into without force or compulsion. God did not have to save Israel. God did not have to covenant with a people. God was not forced to create. He is under no obligation to save. Therefore, the situations that he involves himself in, about which he has these value-laden judgments like anger, sadness, etc, are situations over which he is sovereign and in control.
The Incarnation–Chalcedonian Solutions
“All this theological logic-chopping and conceptional analysis is fine, but what about the cross? Doesn’t that show that God suffers? What sense does it make to say that God is impassible if Jesus is God and Jesus truly suffers on the cross?” This is where a little Chalcedonian christology comes to the rescue.
The classic answer developed by theologians like Cyril of Alexandria is that while it is appropriate to say that the Son suffered on the cross, we make it clear that the God the Son suffered in his humanity, which is capable of suffering. Because we confess the unity of the Godman, that this man, Jesus Christ, truly is the Eternal Son, it is true to say that God suffered, but only in the soul and flesh of the Godman. If we begin to take suffering up into the divine nature, then we begin to render the incarnation a pointless gesture. If God can suffer in his own nature, then why assume human nature at all? In a sense, it is true to say that the lover wills to suffer alongside the beloved. But without impassibility we lose the wonder of what God has done in Christ—he who knew no suffering in himself willed to become as we were so the he could experience it alongside of us. We too often forget that nobody takes Jesus’ life from him—even in his humanity, the Son lays down his life of his own accord. (John 10:18) He is sovereign even over his death and “suffering” at the human hands he empowered to crucify him. (John 19:11) What’s more, he did so not just to “feel our pain” but in order to end it. This is some comfort when we read that Christ is a sympathetic high priest who knows of our temptations (Heb 4:15), but as Vanhoozer reminds us, the true comfort of the verse comes when we read that he did not give in to the temptation, but overcame it for our sake in order to cleanse us from our sins giving us free access to the throne of grace. (4:16; Heb 2:17-18)
The Beauty of the Impassible God
The doctrine of impassibility affirms that God did not incarnate himself of necessity to relieve his own unbearable suffering. His existence as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit is one of perfect, unconquerable, and impassible “light, life, and love.” (Vanhoozer) Instead, in Christ, God freely, willingly, and sovereignly endured suffering, actively making it his own so that ours would be put to an end. To affirm God’s impassibility is to confess that God’s action in Christ is nothing other than the beautifully gratuitous outpouring of his invincible, unsurpassable, enduring love for his wayward creatures—it is the foundation of grace itself.
Soli Deo Gloria
This is a great piece. Tally for yourself one passibilist seriously challenged. (I’m not really a passibilist, but I am sympathetic.)
Yahweh is described as changing His mind often enough that the rejection of anthropomorphism (as an explanation for passages which explicitly and un-asterisk-ly describe His emotions) should at least be considered. Major events are described as being caused by His emotions, even His changing emotions. I’m thinking primarily of Genesis 6:6.
While it’s tidy to sweep this into an anthropomorphic-for-comprehension category, it might not do justice to Yahweh’s extreme (re)action. It strikes me as possible that the Creator would allow Himself to be affected by His creation. Maybe what we see as He floods the earth is a simplified explanation of why He’s doing this which uses human emotional language so the dumb Hebrews could understand. Or maybe what we’re seeing is a Creator so actively involved with His creation that He feels the temporally-bound emotion of regret.
I mean, we can cry at novels even though we have complete control of the timestream of that world. A flick of the wrist and we’re years later or earlier. If the concept of willingly being affected by something smaller, and on a different plane of existence is possible for us, then isn’t also possible that the Bible is simply reporting that the infinite, perfect, and sovereign God allowed Himself to stop and hover over that period?
The text says that He regretted making man. That doesn’t necessarily mean that He is involuntarily affected, like a road rage God. My cat is a lesser being that pisses me off. I don’t lose control and throw her against the wall. But I do have emotions and show them and act against her within the constraints of my value system that I’ve developed over many calm-minded sessions.
So it seems possible that Yahweh could feel and react while maintaining His perfect knowledge, His sovereignty, and His justice.
Conforming that statement, of God regretting His making of man, to an Augustinian assertion of impassibility sounds an awful lot like confining God.
I don’t mean that as a charge against you personally as much as a critique of Reformed theology generally. The walls of possibility must be decided on. Is it tradition, logic, the Bible, or some combination of the three which decides what’s possible? If it’s a combination, then which trumps which and when?
Brief defenses aside, the section which most convicted me is the one regarding the Incarnation-Chalcedonian Solutions. It was considering the Incarnation which first convicted me to reconsider my staunch Reformed Presbyterian theology in the first place. After all, the central point of the Bible, and of history, seems centered on these three events: the Incarnation, Christ’s Crucifixion, and the Resurrection. All dependent on the first. And the Incarnation itself seems to be a pointed expression of God’s immediacy. The Incarnation seems to say that God has slowed His reading (or writing) of the story to interact with it. He’s given up the ability to just flip the pages to the next chapter.
The clean divisions of Christ’s nature have, for the past five or so years, struck me as ironically Western. Chalcedon being even further east than Constantinople, my arrogant review sinks a bit. Still, the tidiness of attributing this or that to Christ’s human nature and this or that to Christ’s divine nature just seems a little scientific. What we’re dealing with is the breaking of the first big rule: God is God, man is man, and that’s that. And it’s the only breaking of this rule ever, so there’s no control to test the multitude of theories. Isn’t it enough to just say that Jesus was the Christ, fully God and fully man? No, I guess it’s not.
Anyway, the line that hit me hardest: “If God can suffer in his own nature, then why assume human nature at all?”
And suddenly the answer man is struck dumb! I must think on this.
Thank you for the awesome paper!
I appreciate this comment, which helped me in my own processing.
The line, “If God can suffer in his own nature, then why assume human nature at all?” is a thought provoking one. I guess I would counter, “How can we say that the human nature is assumed by God in any meaningful sense if we can’t say that the suffering of Christ is the suffering of God?”
I think I’m confused by the line “then why assume human nature at all”. Did Christ come only to suffer? Is suffering per se the heart and the meaning of the incarnation? Certainly it is significant, but I thought the whole conquering death thing was also significant, and I don’t recall that ever having to do with suffering specifically. I should think the incarnation were necessary whether or not the pre-incarnation Trinity can suffer.
One question that does come up, however, is this: now that Chirst has a body (a resurrection body, I grant you), what does that mean for his passibility? What of his relation to time? Okay, maybe we don’t know much about the physics (let alone the physiology) of the New Creation… but any thoughts on this would be interesting.
I think our imagination and language has a lot of influence over how someone might understand God’s emotion. Specifically, we equate strong emotion with passion, and do not distinguish well between chosen affections and received passions. We speak often of things we are “passionate about”, which in that use, more closely aligns with your definition of affection than passion. So with the muddled usage and our limited imagination, it’s easy to see how so many are sympathetic to the “passibilist” view.
To me, the corrective to this is to recognize that God “feels” (or however that works) his chosen affections with greater intensity and purity than I could experience or imagine myself. Or another way, and I think you alluded to this, is to recognize that it is our passions that are more lacking than our affections, and the lack of a lack is completeness.
Also, I learned a new word today! Two if you count impassible and passible separately.
Wow, I really like the way you said this.
To me it seems very Lewisian… our emotions are just a shadow of what they ought to be, the which is a dim reflection of the Godhead.
And to Dr Rishmawy, thank you for this article. It’s wonderful to read something so clearly thought-out that nevertheless inspires the most beautiful of emotions.
I also found helpful your use of impassivity over and against impassibility.
But it all begs the question, why would Moltmann argue as he does? Is he really just arguing that God does have emotion? I suppose I should read the book…
Great points. But, to be fair, many classical theists have described God in ways that have led directly to the misunderstandings you have set out.
[…] Craig discussed the differences between “Calvinism” and Molinism. Second, Derek Rishmawy wrote a thought-provoking piece that defended impassibility, a defense much-needed today. It brought up some thoughts on method […]
[…] the Church Fathers the presupposition of impassibility is precisely the logic behind the cross. As I’ve explained before, God’s impassibility should not be taken to mean that God does not care, or that he has no […]
[…] The author argues that impassibility is misunderstood: […]
[…] while acknowledging the analogical nature of the language, we see grief, anger, and compassion of the Holy One of Israel […]
[…] in the modern, passibilist sense. I think she’d want to sign off on something along these lines, in order to affirm much of what the tradition has held, while not running roughshod over […]
[…] From Mere Orthodoxy: […]
[…] The Beauty of the Impassible God (Or, Is God an Emotional Teenager?) | Mere Orthodoxy […]
[…] This is the metaphysical logic of the Incarnation. God is by nature unchangeable and impassible . He cannot suffer in his nature, so in the incarnation the divine Son really […]
[…] [27] Derek Rishmawy, “The Beauty of the Impassible God (Or, Is God an Emotional Teenager?),” accessed April 24, 2015, http://mereorthodoxy.com/beauty-impassible-god-god-emotional-teenager/. […]
Wow! I just stumbled on this today and have bookmarked it. This is deep stuff for me.
Question: (and perhaps I should re-read and then meditate on the article a bit) how does this tie in with the biblical descriptions which speak about God having wrath against sinners?
[…] What does our Confession mean when we affirm that God is “without…passions” (WCF 2.1)? To learn more, see this article on the doctrine of divine impassibility. […]